Selecciona una palabra y presiona la tecla d para obtener su definición.

  —158→  

ArribaAbajoForum


ArribaAbajoAgainst Dualisms: A Response to Henry Sullivan107

Howard Mancing



Purdue University

In a recent essay entitled «Don Quixote de la Mancha: Analyzable or Unanalyzable?» published in this journal, Henry W. Sullivan makes the case for the psychoanalysis of literary characters. While there is much to ponder in Sullivan's essay, there are two points, both involving dualisms, that I would like to discuss. In the first case, Sullivan argues insightfully and convincingly against an absolute distinction between how we know and think about fictional characters and how we know and think about real people. In the second case, however, Sullivan insists on an absolute (Cartesian) mind-body dualism as a cornerstone of psychoanalytic theory. I would like to repeat and extend Sullivan's argument in the first case, but refute it and deny its validity in the second.


First dualism: Fact/Fiction

Sullivan cites as representative of a certain widely-shared approach Maud Ellmann's insistence that there is an important distinction between a «human being made of flesh and character made of words» (5), a distinction that allows us to make one kind statement about the former but not the latter. Ellmann is not alone in making the real-life/fictional distinction a fundamental matter of ontology. We are all familiar with arguments like hers, having heard   —159→   them often enough specifically with respect to Cervantes. The case made in terms of fictional characters here is part of a larger issue of the supposedly absolute difference between fact and fiction. The apparent need that so many have felt to assert the existence of a clear and absolute boundary between the real and the fictional can be seen in the many attempts to define fictionality, to determine its unique ontological status, or to distinguish meaningfully between real and possible worlds, that have filled the pages of so many books and scholarly journals for decades.

Sullivan counters this position with the argument that what we can know -and how we know it- of fictional characters, historical personages, and living human beings is in most cases very similar. I would extend that argument to say that what we can know -and how we know it- of anything, regardless of whether it is «fact» or «fiction», is in most cases very similar. I base this assertion on what we have come to know about how the human mind works in perceiving and understanding the world and, by extension, in perceiving and understanding texts, as a part of our world.

Richard J. Gerrig's Experiencing Narrative Worlds (1993) is perhaps the most important book on narrative published in recent years; I recommend it as required reading for anyone interested in narrative. Written by a cognitive psychologist who has studied how real readers read real texts in real contexts, Gerrig's book challenges many fundamental tenets of traditional formalist and structuralist narratology. For Gerrig, narrative texts are seen as intimately related to real-life concerns of their readers, rather than as only self-referential, endlessly deferring, traces of absences. Readers are pragmatic beings who construct personally significant understandings of what they read; they are not abstract or implied entities that somehow exist within the text, as a function of the text, or as a textual norm; nor are they passive, empty spaces upon which language and/or ideology inscribes subjectivity.

Gerrig is particularly critical of the «toggle-switch» mentality, the belief that our minds automatically shift from one mode of comprehension to another depending on whether we are reading fiction or nonfiction. We do not practice Coleridge's «willing suspension of disbelief», but rather what Gerrig calls a «willing construction of disbelief» (230). That is, for Gerrig, we first accept what we read as true and only later, and through a conscious and effortful process, reject some or all of it as false108 As regards fictional characters, Sullivan is quite   —160→   correct in arguing that we understand them much as we understand the people who inhabit our everyday existence as well as those who populate history109. Denied access to the total reality of any other person (as to that of ourselves), we always deal with constructs of that person, never with the person him/herself: we assume, infer, compare, imagine, construe, make believe, and thus construct versions of other people110. In real life we can actually observe and interact dialogically with others, taking note of their intonation, gestures, posture, and so forth, as well as reading, hearing and thinking about them; and when we read texts, though we do not have direct perceptual and social access, we use very similar processes to comprehend both fictional and real or historical characters and events. As Baruch Hochman says, «the clues that we take in and use to construct an image of a person are virtually identical in literature and in life» (36)111.

Furthermore, the cumulative and convincing evidence from cognitive and developmental psychology, primatology, and neuroscience is that we understand other people, fictional and otherwise, largely because we develop early in life what is called a «theory of mind»: the ability «to understand what another individual is thinking, to ascribe beliefs, desires, fears and hopes to someone else, and to believe that they really do experience these feelings as mental states» (Dunbar 83)112. It is this ability that makes social interactions -and the understanding of historical figures and literary characters- possible.

  —161→  

Nicholas Humphrey employs the metaphor of «the inner eye» to discuss the fact that we only have direct access (partial and distorted as it may be) to our own thought processes and emotions. With this reflexive self-awareness, we can also then imagine what it must be like to be someone else; we can model on ourselves the behavior, thoughts, emotions, and feelings of other human beings -and fictional characters113. This is very similar to the «sympathetic understanding» of Bakhtin: «not a mirroring, but a fundamentally and essentially new valuation, a utilization of my own architectonic position in being outside another's inner life. Sympathetic understanding recreates the whole inner person in aesthetically loving categories for a new existence in a new dimension of the world» (102-03). Humphrey further maintains that our culture makes available to us on a regular basis the experiences of other individuals by means of what he calls «institutionalized fantasy: books, plays, music, paintings, films» (1986, 132). The ability to sympathize and empathize with others, to imagine the reality of others -imaginatively to create the reality of other persons- is one of the qualities that most distinguishes humans from other animals and from machines114 and makes the arts in general, and literature in particular, an essential facet of human life.

All of this suggests that Sullivan is correct in his assertion that fictional characters are every bit as susceptible to psychoanalytic understanding as are human beings of flesh and blood. The question not raised by Sullivan, however, is the degree to which human beings can be understood by means of psychoanalysis.




Second dualism: Mind/Body

Sullivan posits as an essential part of his psychoanalytic plea that «human animals and human beings are not the same thing» (9). In his Lacanian terminology, Sullivan states that:

  —162→  

it emerges that the human «being» as an animal «made of flesh» (Ellmann), belongs to the order of the Real. The human subject made of language corresponds to the intermesh of being, founded in the Imaginary, and its subsequent, ego-splitting sublation into the order of meaning in the Symbolic. The human organism and the body, therefore, are not the same thing. What we commonly call the body is, paradoxically, an equivalence of the Imaginary. Indeed, as stated, the very idea of a body is an image that is formed in the Lacanian mirror stage, an image which furnishes a fundamental aspect of the structure of subjectivity.


(10)115                


There are two points to be noted here. First, there is the supposed distinction between the body and the human organism. Apparently such a distinction is important for Lacan, but as far as most of the rest of the world is concerned, the word «body» is a perfectly acceptable -in fact, the preferred- term for the «human organism». In what follows here I use the term «body» specifically in its straightforward, standard sense as referring to the organism of flesh and bone -the living, breathing human being who exists in the material world: the human organism- whether that usage is acceptable to Lacan (and Sullivan) or not. Second, Sullivan insists that the biological body is radically and absolutely separate from the mind (in Lacanian terms, the human «subject» as constructed by language). Sullivan's, like Lacan's, aim is «to 'debiologize' human subjects» (14)116. No clearer or more unequivocal reaffirmation of Cartesian mind-body dualism is possible. And this is what I want to reject.

Modern biology, neuroscience, evolutionary science, cognitive psychology, and linguistics have virtually no use for any version of mind-body dualism. Today we make use of concepts like the «embodied mind», «the body in the mind», and the «mind-brain»117. It is   —163→   impossible to separate cognition and emotion, what the body feels and what the brain thinks.118 The mere fact of speaking, for example, has a direct and significant effect on blood pressure119. In today's cognitive science, the prevailing view of human consciousness prominently involves memory, feedback loops, mental imagery, emotion, inner speech, social context, dialogue, representation, and mind-body interaction; it is an emergent, nonlinear, autopoietic, contingent, contextualized, dynamic function or process120. Consciousness is «a very special emergent property of the human brain... made possible by a sufficient number of parallel interacting modules» (Restak 135)121. There is an unbroken continuum from the very molecules of our physical makeup through society at large. In the words of Ira B. Black:

  —164→  

Biology becomes behavior, and behavior becomes biology. Indeed, biology is behavior, and behavior is biology. Environmental or internal exigencies drive the locus and are translated into biologic reality. Thoughts or environmental situations provoking anxiety are immediately translated into neural language. Environmental stimulus, mental state, behavior, and molecular mechanisms are in constant interplay, forming an unbroken, continuous cycle.


(167)122                


Self, mind, brain, body, environment: all interact at every point along the unbroken continuum that makes up reality123. Neurologist Antonio Damasio, in what almost seems like a direct refutation of the Lacanian position, writes:

This is Descartes' error: the abyssal separation between body and mind, between the sizable, dimensioned, mechanically operated, infinitely divisible body stuff, on the one hand, and the unsizable, undimensioned, up-pushpullable, nondivisible mind stuff; the suggestion that reasoning, and moral judgment, and the suffering that comes from physical pain or emotional upheaval might exist separately from the body. Specifically: the separation of the most refined operations of mind from the structure and operation of a biological organism.


(249-50; emphasis added)                


The centrality of mind-body dualism to psychoanalytic thought is clearly a major -some would say fatal- shortcoming124. Of a kind   —165→   is the distinction made by Freud et al. between the conscious and unconscious minds, the latter a seething cauldron of sexual obsessions that controls much of our life from within its hidden underground. Modern cognitive psychology and neuroscience have little room for the traditional psychoanalytic unconscious and have substituted for it the «cognitive unconscious», that array of cognitive functions that goes on all the time in our mind-brain without our conscious awareness: the regulation of breathing and blood pressure; primary emotional reactions; reactions to many visual, auditory, and olfactory perceptions; our haptic sense; background beliefs and emotions; the schemata that make it possible to perceive things as we do; and much more125. Freudian dream theory now competes unfavorably with the simpler and more powerful «activation-synthesis» theory that is based in biology and neuroscience126. Sophisticated recent research in sociology, anthropology, infant cognition, and child development has produced results that bear little, if any, resemblance to the models suggested by Freud -anal and oral stages, the Oedipal complex- or Lacan -the so-called «mirror stage»127. Repression is one of Freud's foundational concepts that has undergone the most devastating criticism at the hands of the modern understanding of the human mind-brain128. Little wonder that a major neuroscientist such as Michael Gazzaniga has written on «Selection Theory and the Death of Psychoanalysis» (159-77)129.

  —166→  

I am not suggesting that there is absolutely no validity to any type of psychoanalytic theory,130 but I am suggesting that it is perhaps time, at the dawn of the twenty-first century, to reexamine some of the nineteenth- and early twentieth-century concepts that form the bases of that theory. Recent research in mind and brain empowers us with a set of concepts and a verifiable basis in observation about the nature of human consciousness, cognition, and emotion that cannot legitimately be ignored in the construction and application of theories in the human sciences. To the extent that Freudian and/or Lacanian theories can be understood as consistent with modern neuroscience and cognitive science, they will be considered valid and useful.




Conclusion

In general, dualistic thought -and especially its crown jewel, Cartesian mind-body dualism- is not consistent with modern concepts of human perception and cognition. Cervantine studies have certainly been characterized by their fair share of simplistic binary thinking: Quijote/Sancho, reality/appearance, hard/soft, romance/novel, fact/fiction, and much more. Such absolute distinctions in kind tend not to exist in the world, but only in our theories and beliefs. The Aristotelian bedrock of A vs. not-A has, in modern cognitive science, been replaced by fuzzy sets, human-made boundaries, and prototype theories of categorization131. The world exists not in stark contrasts of black and white but in subtle and shifting shades   —167→   of gray. Sullivan realizes this and convincingly affirms it in his discussion of the fact/fiction binary, but fails to see it and, as a result, fails to convince in his insistence of the traditional mind/body distinction.

My aim in this response has been less to criticize Henry Sullivan, a brilliant scholar whom I admire, than to suggest that there is, outside of the narrow confines of the predominant paradigms of poststructuralist and psychoanalytic literary theory, an important and largely ignored (by literary scholars) view of the human being that is grounded in modern research in biology and psychology. This «response» has been, as much as anything, a preliminary essay in alternative bibliography132.

Sullivan affirms that «the only discipline in the post-Modern era that takes the psyche -psyche or soul- seriously as the scientific object of its study is psychoanalysis» (19). Except for the unsustainable (and unnecessary) claim of scientific status for psychoanalysis, Sullivan is largely correct in this statement. But it can be stated with even greater justification that at the close of the twentieth century the discipline that takes the embodied mind as the scientific object of its study is cognitive science. The vast interdisciplinary activity centered around cognitive science has enormous implications for literary theory and criticism and it will be ignored at our great peril as it continues to form the prevailing mode of discourse of the physical, biological, social, and human sciences in the twenty-first century.



  —168→  
Works Cited

Ammaniti, Massimo and Daniel N. Stern, eds. Psychoanalysis and Development: Representations and Narratives. New York: New York UP, 1994.

Anderson, Joseph D. The Reality of Illusion: An Ecological Approach to Cognitive Film Theory. Carbondale: Southern Illinois UP, 1996.

Baars, Bernard J. In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind. New York: Oxford, 1997.

Babuts, Nicolae. The Dynamics of the Metaphoric Field: A Cognitive View of Literature. Newark: U of Delaware P, 1992.

Bakhtin, M. M. Art and Answerability: Early Philosophical Essays. Ed. Michael Holquist and Vadim Liapunov. Trans. and notes Vadim Liapunov. Supplement trans. Kenneth Brostrom. Austin: U of Texas P, 1990.

Barron, James W., Morris N. Eagle, and David L. Wolitzky, eds. Interface of Psychoanalysis and Psychology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 1992.

Battersby, James L. Paradigms Regained; Pluralism and the Practice of Criticism. Philadelphia: U of Pennsylvania P, 1991.

Bechtel, William. «Embodied Connectionism». In The Future of the Cognitive Revolution. Ed. David Martel Johnson and Christina E. Erneling. New York: Oxford UP, 1997. 187-208.

Black, Ira B. Information in the Brain: A Molecular Perspective. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1990.

Bordwell, David. Making Meaning: Inference and Rhetoric in the Interpretation of Film. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1989.

——. Narration in the Fiction Film. Madison: U of Wisconsin P, 1985.

Bordwell, David and Noël Carroll, eds. Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies. Madison: U of Wisconsin P, 1996.

  —169→  

Boruah, Bijoy H. Fiction and Emotion: A Study in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon P, 1988.

Bucci, Wilma. Cognitive Science and Psychoanalysis: A Multiple Code Theory. New York: Guilford P, 1997.

Byrne, Richard W. and Andrew Whiten, eds. Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes, and Humans. Oxford: Clarendon P, 1988.

Calvin, William H. The Cerebral Symphony: Seashore Reflections on the Structure of Consciousness. New York: Bantam, 1990.

Carroll, Joseph. Evolution and Literary Theory. Columbia: U of Missouri P, 1995.

Carroll, Noël. Mystifying Mories: Fads and Fallacies in Contemporary Film Theory. New York: Columbia UP, 1988.

——. Philosophical Problems of Classical Film Theory. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1988.

Carruthers, Peter and Peter K. Smith, eds. Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1996.

Caudill, Maureen. In Our Own Image: Building an Artificial Person. New York: Oxford UP, 1992.

Clark, Andy. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1997.

——. «Where Brain, Body, and World Collide». Daedalus 127.2 (1998): 257-80.

Clark, Andy and David Chalmers. «The Extended Mind». Analysis 58 (1998): 7-19.

Code, Lorraine. What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1991.

Collins, Christopher. The Poetics of the Mind's Eye: Literature and the Psychology of Imagination. Philadelphia: U of Pennsylvania P, 1991.

Crawford, Mary and Roger Chaffin. «The Reader's Construction of Meaning: Cognitive Research on Gender and Comprehension». In Gender and Reading: Essays on Readers, Texts, and Contexts. Ed. Elizabeth A. Flynn and Patrocinio P. Schweickart. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1986. 3-30.

Crews, Fredrick C. et al. The Memory Wars: Freud's Legacy in Dispute. New York: New York Review, 1995.

Currie, Gregory. Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1995.

Daly, Martin and Margo Wilson. Homicide. New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1988.

Damasio, Antonio R. Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam, 1994.

  —170→  

Deacon, Terrence W. The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Brain. New York: W. W. Norton, 1997.

Dennett, Daniel C. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1991.

Donald, Merlin. The Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1991.

Dreyfus, Hubert L. and Stuart E. Dreyfus, with Tom Athanasiou. Mind over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer. New York: Free P, 1986.

Dunbar, Robin. Grooming, Gossip, and the Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1996.

DuPreez, Peter. A Science of Mind: The Quest for Psychological Reality. London: Academic P, 1990.

Edelman, Gerald M. Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. New York: Basic Books, 1992.

Eiser, J. Richard. Attitudes, Chaos and the Connectionist Mind. Oxford: Blackwell, 1994.

Epstein, Seymour. «Integration of the Cognitive and the Psychodynamic Unconscious». American Psychologist 49 (1994): 709-24.

Epstein, William M. The Illusion of Psychotherapy. New Brunswick: Trancaction Publishers, 1995.

Erdelyi, Matthew Hugh. Psychoanalysis: Freud's Cognitive Psychology. New York: W. H. Freeman, 1985.

Erwin, Edward. A Final Accounting: Philosophical and Empirical Issues in Freudian Psychology. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1996.

Esrock, Ellen J. The Reader's Eye: Visual Imaging as Reader Response. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1994.

Esterson, Allen. Seductive Mirage: An Exploration of the Work of Sigmund Freud. Chicago: Open Court, 1993.

Fancher, Robert T. Cultures of Healing: Correcting the Image of American Mental Health Care. New York: W. H. Freeman, 1995.

Fischer, Roland. «Emergence of Mind from Brain: The Biological Roots of the Hermeneutic Circle». Diogenes 138 (1987): 1-25.

Flanagan, Owen. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1992.

Franklin, Stan. Artificial Minds. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1997.

Frye, Joanne S. Living Stories, Telling Lives: Women and the Novel in Contemporary Experience. Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P, 1986.

Galatzer-Levy, Robert M. and Bertram J. Cohler. The Essential Other: A Developmental Psychology of the Self. New York: Basic Books, 1993.

  —171→  

Gazzaniga, Michael S. Nature's Mind: The Biological Roots of Thinking, Emotions, Sexuality, Language, and Intelligence. New York: Basic Books, 1992.

Gee, James Paul. The Social Mind: Language, Ideology, and Social Practice. Foreword Donaldo Macedo. New York: Bergin and Garvey, 1992.

Gelernter, David. The Muse in the Machine: Computerizing the Poetry of Human Thought. New York: Free P, 1994.

Gergen, Kenneth J. The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life. New York: Basic Books, 1991.

——. «Textual Considerations in the Scientific Construction of Human Character». Style 24 (1990): 365-79.

Gergen, Kenneth J. and Keith E. Davis, eds. The Social Construction of the Person. New York: Springer, 1985.

Gerrig, Richard J. Experiencing Narrative Worlds: On the Psychological Activities of Reading. New Haven: Yale UP, 1993.

Gerrig, Richard J. and David W. Allbritton. «The Construction of Literary Character: A View from Cognitive Psychology». Style 24 (1990): 380-91.

Gibson, James J. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1979.

——. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966.

Gilbert, Daniel T. «How Mental Systems Believe». American Psychologist 46 (1991): 107-19.

Gordon, Robert M. The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1987.

Graham, Joseph F. Onomatopoetics: Theory of Language and Literature. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992.

Grünbaum, Adolf. The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique. Berkeley: U of California P, 1984.

Harris, Jay E. Clinical Neuroscience: From Neuroanatomy to Psychodynamics. New Your: Human Sciences P, 1986.

Hart, F. Elizabeth. «Cognitive Linguistics: The Experiential Dynamics of Metaphor». Mosaic 28 (1995): 1-23.

Harth, Erich. The Creative Loop: How the Brain Makes a Mind. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1993.

Hermans, Hubert J. M. and Harry J. G. Kempen. The Dialogical Self: Meaning as Movement. San Diego: Academic P, 1993.

Herring, Henry D. «Constructivist Interpretation: An Alternative to Deconstruction». In Text, Interpretation, Theory. Ed. James M. Heath and Michael Payne. Lewisburg: Bucknell UP, 1985. 32-46.

  —172→  

Hobson, J. Allan. The Dreaming Brain. New York: Basic Books, 1988.

Hochman, Baruch. Character in Literature. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1985.

Holland, Norman N. The Brain of Robert Frost: A Cognitive Approach to Literature. New York: Routledge, 1988.

——. The Critical I. New York: Columbia UP, 1992.

Humphrey, Nicholas. Consciousness Regained: Chapters in the Development of Mind. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1983.

——. A History of the Mind. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1992.

——. The Inner Eye. Illus. Mel Calman. London: Faber and Faber, 1986.

Jackendoff, Ray. Patterns in the Mind: Language and Human Nature. New York: Basic Books, 1994.

Johnson, Mark. The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1987.

——. «Knowing through the Body». Philosophical Psychology 4 (1991): 3-18.

——. Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1993.

Johnson-Laird, P. N. Mental Models: Towards a Cognitive Science of Language Inference and Consciousness. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1983.

Kihlstrom, John F. «The Cognitive Unconscious». Science 237 (1987): 1445-52.

——. «The Psychological Unconscious». In Handbook of Personality: Theory and Research. Ed. Lawrence A. Pervin. New York: Giulford P, 1990. 445-64.

Kitcher, Patricia. Freud's Dream: A Complete Interdisciplinary Science of Mind. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1992.

Kosko, Bart. Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of Fuzzy Logic. New York: Hyperion, 1993.

Kosslyn, Stephen M. «Freud Returns?» In The Science of the Mind: 2001 and Beyond. Ed. Robert L. Solso and Dominic W. Massaro. New York: Oxford UP, 1995. 90-106.

Lakoff, George. «The Neurocognitive Self: Conceptual System Research in the Twenty-first Century and the Rethinking of What a Person Is». In The Science of the Mind: 2001 and Beyond. Ed. Robert L. Solso and Dominic W. Massaro. New York: Oxford UP, 1995. 221-43.

——. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1987.

Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1980.

Lakoff, George and Mark Turner. More than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1989.

  —173→  

LeDoux, Joseph. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996.

Lindsay, D. Stephen and John D. Read. «Psychotherapy and Memories of Childhood Sexual Abuse; A Cognitive Perspective». Applied Cognitive Psychology 8 (1994): 281-338.

Lloyd, Dan. Simple Minds. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1989.

Loftus, Elizabeth F. «The Reality of Repressed Memories». American Psychologist 48 (1993): 518-37.

Lynch, James J. The Language of the Heart: The Body's Response to Human Dialogue. New York: Basic Books, 1985.

Madison, G. B. «The Hermeneutics of (Inter)subjectivity, or: The Mind/Body Problem Deconstructed». Man and World 21 (1988): 3-33.

Masling, Joseph M. and Robert F. Bornstein, eds. Psychoanalytic Perspectives on Developmental Psychology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 1996.

Maturana, Humberto R. and Francisco J. Varela. The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Rev. ed. Foreword J. Z. Young. Bonston: Shambhala, 1992.

Messaris, Paul. Visual «Literacy»: Image, Mind, and Reality. Boulder: Westview P, 1994.

Mithen, Steven. The Prehistory of the Mind: The Cognitive Origins of Art, Religion and Science. London: Thames and Hudson, 1996.

Modell, Arnold H. Other Times, Other Realities: Toward a Theory of Psychoanalytic Treatment. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1990.

Nadeau, Robert L. Mind, Machines, and Human Consciousness. Chicago: Contemporary Books, 1991.

Neisser, Ulric. Cognition and Reality: Principles and Implications of Cognitive Psychology. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1976.

——. «Five Kinds of Self-knowledge». Philosophical Psychology 1 (1988): 35-59.

——, ed. The Perceived Self: Ecological and Interpersonal Sources of Self-Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1993.

Neisser, Ulric and Robyn Fivush, eds. The Remembering Self: Construction and Accuracy in the Self-Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994.

Nelson, Katherine. Language in Cognitive Development: Emergence of the Mediated Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1996.

Norman, Donald A. Things that Make Us Smart: Defending Human Attributes in the Age of the Machine. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1993.

Oatley, Keith. Best Laid Schemes: The Psychology of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992.

  —174→  

Ofshe, Richard and Ethan Watters. Making Monsters: False Memories, Psychotherapy, and Sexual Hysteria. New York: Scribner's, 1994.

Ornstein, Robert. The Evolution of Consciousness: Of Darwin, Freud, and Cranial Fire: The Origins of the Way We Think. New York: Prentice-Hall, 1991.

——. The Roots of the Self: Unraveling the Mystery of Who We Are. San Francisco: Harper, 1995.

Ortony, Andrew, Gerald L. Clore, and Allan Collins. The Cognitive Structure of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1988.

Pinker, Steven. How the Mind Works. New York: Norton, 1997.

Ratner, Carl. «The Unconscious: A Perspective from Sociohistorical Psychology». Journal of Mind and Behavior 15 (1994): 323-42.

Reber, Arthur S. Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious. New York: Oxford UP, 1993.

Reed, Edward S. James J. Gibson and the Psychology of Perception. New Haven: Yale UP, 1988.

Reiser, Morton F. Memory in Mind and Brain: What Dream Imagery Reveals. New York: Basic Books, 1990.

Restak, Richard M. The Modular Brain: How New Discoveries in Neuroscience Are Answering Age-Old Questions about Memory, Free Will, Consciousness, and Personal Identity. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1994.

Rigney, Ann. «The Point of Stories: On Narrative Communication and its Cognitive Functions». Poetics Today 13 (1992): 263-83.

Rosch, Eleanor. «Human Categorization». In Studies in Cross-Cultural Psychology, Vol. 1. Ed. Neil Warren. London: Academic P, 1977. 1-49.

——. «Principles of Categorization». In Cognition and Categorization. Ed. Eleanor Rosch and Barbara B. Lloyd. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1978. 27-48.

Rosch, Eleanor and Carolyn B. Mervis. «Family Resemblances: Studies in the Internal Structure of Categories». Cognitive Psychology 7 (1975): 573-605.

Rubin, David C. Memory in Oral Traditions: The Cognitive Psychology of Epic, Ballads, and Counting-out Rhymes. New York: Oxford UP, 1995.

Schacter, Daniel L. Searching for Memory: The Brain, the Mind, and the Past. New York: Basic Books, 1996.

Schmidt, Siegfried J. «The Empirical Science of Literature ESL: A New Paradigm». Poetics 12 (1983): 19-34.

——. «The Fiction Is that Reality Exists: A Constructivist Model of Reality, Fiction, and Literature». Poetics Today 5 (1984): 253-74.

  —175→  

——. «Foundations of a Constructivist Empirical Study of Literature». Reader 14 (1985): 5-22.

——. «Interpretation: Sacred Cow or Necessity?» Poetics 12 (1983): 239-58.

Schwalbe, Michael L. «The Autogenesis of the Self». Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 21 (1991): 269-95.

Schwarz, Daniel R. The Case for a Humanistic Poetics. Philadelphia: U of Pennsylvania P, 1991.

Scott, Alwyn. Stairway to the Mind: The Controversial New Science of Consciousness. New York: Copernicus, 1995.

Searle, John R. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1992.

Shaw, Robert and John Bransford, eds. Perceiving, Acting, and Knowing: Toward an Ecological Psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1977.

Siebenschuh, William R. Fictional Techniques and Factual Works. Athens: U of Georgia P, 1983.

Smith, Murray. Engaging Characters: Fiction, Emotion, and the Cinema. Oxford: Clarendon P, 1995.

Smith, Paul. Discerning the Subject. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1988.

Solso, Robert L. Cognition and the Visual Arts. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT P, 1994.

Soper, Kate. Humanism and Anti-Humanism. London: Hutchinson, 1986.

Spence, Donald P. The Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis: Displacement of Evidence by Theory. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1994.

Spolsky, Ellen. Gaps in Nature: Literary Interpretation and the Modular Mind. Albany: State U of New York P, 1993.

Stafford, Barbara Maria. Good Looking: Essays on the Virtue of Images. Cambridge: MIT P, 1996.

States, Bert O. Hamlet and the Concept of Character. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1992.

Stern, Daniel N. The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic Books, 1985.

Storey, Robert. Mimesis and the Human Animal: On the Biogenetic Foundations of Literary Representation. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1996.

Sullivan, Henry W. «Don Quixote de la Mancha: Analyzable or Unanalyzable?» Cervantes 18 (1998): 4-23.

Thelen, Esther and Linda Smith. A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge: MIT P, 1994.

  —176→  

Tooby, John and Leda Cosmides. «The Psychological Foundations of Culture». In The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Ed. Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides and John Tooby. New York: Oxford UP, 1992. 19-136.

Turner, Mark. Death Is the Mother of Beauty: Mind, Metaphor, Criticism. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1987.

——. The Literary Mind. New York: Oxford UP, 1996.

——. Reading Minds: The Study of English in the Age of Cognitive Science. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1991.

Varela, Francisco J. , Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge: MIT P, 1993.

Vauclair, Jacques. Animal Cognition: An Introduction to Modern Comparative Psychology. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1996.

Voloshinov, V. N. [M. M. Bakhtin]. Freudianism: A Critical Sketch. Ed. I. R. Titunik and Neil R. Bruss. Trans. I. R. Titunik. Bloomington: Indiana UP, 1987.

Vygotsky, L. S. Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes. Ed. Michael Cole, Vera John-Steiner, Sylvia Scribner, and Ellen Souberman. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1978.

Weiskrantz, Larry, ed. Thought without Language. New York: Oxford UP, 1988.

Whiten, Andrew, ed. Natural Theories of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.

Winson, Jonathan. Brain and Psyche: The Biology of the Unconscious. Garden City, NY: Anchor P/Doubleday, 1985.

Wojciehowski, Dolora A. Old Masters, New Subjects: Early Modern and Poststructuralist Theories of Will. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1995.

Wolfe, Alan. The Human Difference: Animals, Computers, and the Necessity of Social Science. Berkeley: U of California P, 1993.

Zadeh, Lotfi A. «Fuzzy Sets». Information and Control 8 (1965): 338-53.

Zerubavel, Eviatar. The Fine Line: Making Distinctions in Everyday Life. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1991.